Das Unwahre aber ist unbegreiflich


After a break got to finish the second chapter of the first part (Bestimmtheit – Qualität) of the first book (Die Lehre vom Sein) of Science of Logic this morning. So this is Das Dasein chapter (from Sein – Das Dasein – Das Fürsichsein trio). By far the most interesting discussion so far, I think, is not the usually brought up Being-Nothing-Becoming (Sein-Nichts-Werden) from the first chapter (Sein) but finitude and infinitude sections.

The second chapter – in di Giovanni’s new SL translation, it is “Existence” but more familiar in the old version as “Determinate Being” – ends with a short “Transition” paragraph (and two Remarks). There is some German weirdness that I cannot quite understand here – so here it is…

If you read di Giovanni’s translation carefully, you’ll see that there is an interesting problem of translation (I can only guess that this is a deliberate choice):

Transition
Ideality can be called the quality of the infinite; but it is essentially the
process of becoming, and hence a transition – like the transition of becoming (Werden) into existence (Dasein). We must now explicate this transition. This immanent turning back, as the sublating of finitude (als Aufheben der Endlichkeit) – that is, of finitude as such and equally of the negative finitude that only stands opposite to it, is only negative finitude – is self-reference, being. Since there is negation in this being, the latter is existence; but, further, since the negation is essentially negation of the negation, self-referring negation, it is the existence that
carries the name of being-for-itself.

The bolded part has “negative finitude” (twice) where the German has the term “infinitude” (once) – but it seems that di Giovanni corrects Hegel in suggesting his meant finitude since negated finitude is infinitude, so that which stands against finitude should be negative finitude (not negative infinitude).

Der Ubergang
Die Idealität kann die Qualität der Unendlichkeit genannt werden; aber sie ist wesentlich der Prozeß des Werdens und damit ein Übergang, wie des Werdens in Dasein, der nun anzugeben ist. Als Aufheben der Endlichkeit, d. i. der Endlichkeit als solcher und ebensosehr der ihr nur gegenüberstehenden, nur negativen Unendlichkeit ist diese Rückkehr in sichBeziehung auf sich selbst, Sein. Da in diesem Sein Negation ist, ist es Dasein, aber da sie ferner wesentlich Negation der Negation, die sich auf sich beziehende Negation ist, ist sie das Dasein, welches Fürsichsein genannt wird.

However, there seems to be no adjective + noun construction in German – so there is neither “negative finitude” nor “negative infinitude” – in the  German text we have der ihr nur gegenüberstehenden, nur negativen or if we take one clause out der ihr nur negativen = “ihr” is dative of “sie” and relates to “der Endlichkeit” – so “to it only opposite, only negative, infinitude” sounds like a good version.

Here is A.V. Miller’s translation:

Transition

Ideality can be called the quality of infinity; but it is essentially the process of becoming, and hence a transition – like that of becoming in determinate being – which is now to be indicated. As a sublating of finitude, that is, finitude as such, and equally of the infinitude which is merely its opposite, merely negative, this return into self is self-relation, being. As this being contains negation it is determinate, but as this negation further is essentially negation of the negation, the self-related negation, it is that determinate being which is called being-for-itself.

Miller’s translation takes (again, it seems to me, correctly and better than di Giovanni) this phrase and breaks it down this way = und ebensosehr [der ihr nur gegenüberstehenden, nur negativen] Unendlichkeit. That is, “and equally of (only standing opposite it, only negative) infinitude” – but I leave this up to those who are better at German than me…

 

On Dramatic Exits From Academia


UPDATE: I guess there is more drama here than I thought – maybe this one deserves a dramatic exit?

To complicate matters, a few years before Ms. Chant came up for tenure she had had an affair with a philosopher outside Missouri, and Mr. Ernst, who was crushed at the time, is said to have told a colleague here that he actually wrote most of his wife’s work. Mr. Ernst now says that’s something he never claimed, but Ms. Chant says she believes that it was a factor in her tenure proceedings.

This post by Zachary Ernst (a great Public Radio announcer name, by the way, in case he’s looking for a cool job now that he is out of academia) has been going around = Why I Jumped Off The Ivory Tower:

I’m leaving my position as a tenured Associate Professor of Philosophy and taking a job in the private sector. By any normal standards, my academic job was excellent. I was tenured at a Research-1 institution, in a department with a growing PhD program. I had a lot of freedom to pursue the kind of research and teaching that I wanted. And I used that freedom to pursue a lot of diverse interests. My students — especially my graduate students — were excellent. I enjoy teaching, and I also happen to believe that philosophy is increasingly important and relevant.

It’s an interesting read, including some of the issues related to higher education in general. However it strikes me as overly dramatic since it present the decision to leave academia as some sort of earth-crushingly life-changing event of gigantic importance. Needless to say, it is a brave move in and of itself since Ernst has tenure and is basically guaranteed employment and salary for the rest of his life. That he find this unsatisfactory and openly admits to it is an honest move and I think most people feel that it is not a pose. But, at the same time, hundreds (if not thousands) are leaving academia every year – I’m talking about graduate students who get their degrees and are not able to find full-time employment, as well as adjuncts who give up and stop teaching – and yet their exits are sort of a matter of academic life.

The reasons that Ernst lists are not really the sorts of reasons many of these unlucky unemployed academics would actually mind. “Academia discourages interdisciplinary research and my department head is kind of a dick” (paraphrase) – is that really so bad?

One aspect of all the dramatic accounts of exits from academia that I do not understand is that they so clearly reinforce the narrative of academic paradise that the folks who are leaving are criticizing – an academic job is thought of as such a desirable job that leaving it voluntarily surely requires a long and elaborate explanation. No one writes a post “Why I Am Leaving McDonalds” or “Why I Decided To Look for Another Mid-Level Management Position” – do they?

I have been teaching at my institutions as an adjunct ever since I was a graduate student – it’s been seven years and I took one year off for a full-time lectureship elsewhere. I have a full-time regular job so I don’t need the income and mostly teach because I enjoy the distraction (and an institutional affiliation with a library access). When I leave (and I will since there is no prospect of the full-time job) no one will really notice since all I have to do is to forget to fill out my preference sheet for the upcoming semester. No “retirement party” will be held, no announcement will be made. Some other adjunct will quietly take my place and I will move on with my life.

It’s a job change just like any other job change – you quit academia, you start something else. I don’t think there needs to be so much drama around it. Right?

“Darwin Rocks Hegel: Does Nature Have a History?” (David Kolb)


Here is a nice essay on Hegel and Darwin (obviously Hegel died long before The Origin of Species, but I always wondered about possible connections):

The way current debates get publicised, there appear to be two extreme positions. The first is a reductionist materialism: all complex systems are describable purely in terms of the qualities of their most basic components, and the systems themselves result from Darwinian selection. No teleological concepts at all need be applied. At the other extreme is total teleology; all systems and their interactions and development are the result of preconceived conscious purposeful design by a powerful designer. The ontological status of the designer is usually filled out with theological notions.

Here is a section from Stephen Houlgate’s An Introduction to Hegel, Freedom, Truth and History where he presents Hegel’s anti-evolutionary positions (Hegel would have been familiar with Lamarck’s theory):

Given Hegel’s commitment to a synchronic rather than diachronic understanding of nature and life, it is clear that he would have had no greater interest in the Darwinian theory of evolution than in the Lamarckian theory. Pace Findlay, Hegel in the Philosophy of Nature is not ‘a philosopher of evolution’. There is a difference, however, between a lack of interest in something and outright hostility to it, and I see nothing in the very idea of speculative philosophy that justifies Hegel in rejecting, rather than simply beingindifferent to, the idea of the evolution of species. It is quite possible to focus one’s own philosophical attention on the logical, structural differences between species, but also to allow other scientists to study the process whereby such species emerged in time (just as it is possible to let scientists study the origins of the solar system and of life). In my view, therefore, Hegel’s philosophy of nature is not in principle incompatible with either the general idea of the evolution of species or Darwin’s particular theory of evolution by natural selection.

Brandom on Hegel: “Knowing and Representing: Reading (between the lines of) Hegel’s Introduction”


The lectures were given 30 May – 1 June, 2011, at Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität. The text of the lectures is found on Brandom’s website (click on titles to get Word document versions):

Lecture One, “Conceptual Realism and the Semantic Possibility of Knowledge”:

Lecture Two, “Representation and the Experience of Error: A Functionalist Approach to the Distinction between Appearance and Reality”:

Lecture Three, “Following the Path of Despair to a Bacchanalian Revel: The Emergence of the Second, True, Object”:

Confronting Crisis: Left Praxis in the Face of Austerity, War and Revolution Historical Materialism Conference York University, Toronto, Canada May 8-11th, 2014


cropped-Hmlogox

 

Confronting Crisis: Left Praxis in the Face of Austerity, War and Revolution
Historical Materialism Conference
York University, Toronto, Canada
May 8-11th, 2014

Confronted with a global context of austerity, exploitation, imperialist aggression, ongoing colonialism, and ecological crises, the world has been witness to growing social and political struggles over the past decade. A wide range of rural- and urban-based labour and social movements have fought back against the current ‘Age of Austerity,’ while new modes and geographies of resistance against dispossession and tyranny continue to inspire social change in the Global South. Against this backdrop, the 2014 Historical Materialism conference at Toronto’s York University invites proposals for papers, panels, and other kinds of conference participation that can contribute to a collective discussion on how to extend and revitalize Left critique and praxis in the current conjuncture.

We particularly encourage submissions that address the challenges and contradictions facing global anti-capitalist theory and action in the present. Some of the questions the conference strives to address include:

(Theme 1) What are the ideological blind spots of Left thought and practice, and how might they be redressed?

(Theme 2) How does the present historical moment challenge our understanding of the making of the modern global ‘working class’?

(Theme 3) How can Marxist theory be transformed to integrate an understanding of corporeality, identity and subjectivity in its analysis of capitalism and class politics?

(Theme 4) How might historical materialist theory account for the co-constitutive relationship between race, class, gender and sexuality, and what are the implications of such analysis for Left praxis?

(Theme 5) What are the contributions of anti-colonial struggles for internationalist Left politics and praxis today?

(Theme 6) What contributions and challenges do struggles for indigenous self-determination make to Marxist thought and vice versa?

(Theme 7) How can we read Marxist texts politically in the current conjuncture?

(Theme 8) What is the role of space, land, and urbanization in the development and crisis of imperialist, neo-colonial capitalism?

(Theme 9) What is the role of different modes of organization (e.g. parties, unions, student and social movements), and what challenges do they face in the fight against austerity?

(Theme 10) How might we conceptualize new modes of resistance, including the recent upsurge of revolutionary and counter-revolutionary currents, in the Global South?

(Theme 11) What is the specific role of spatial organization in the institution, reproduction and transformation of forms of imperialist, neo-colonial domination and relations of war?

(Theme 12) What are the contributions and challenges of anti-imperialist and anti-capitalist politics to existing ecological crises?

(Theme 13) How can historical materialism assist us in understanding the dynamics of agrarian change under contemporary capitalism, particularly the global food crisis?

(Theme 14) How might historical materialist theory account for the dialectics of the rural and urban geographies of accumulation, domination, and resistance?

(Theme 15) What roles might culture, art and aesthetics play in confronting the crisis of capitalism and building Left movements?

The organizing committee specifically welcomes panel proposals that directly address the above questions. To make a submission for a panel, please include a working title and anabstract of no more than 300 words for the panel, along with the individual paper titles andabstracts of no more than 300 words. Please make sure to also include the names, email addresses and academic affiliations of all panelists.

For individual submissions, please include a working title, an abstract of no more than 300 words, as well as your name, email address and academic affiliation.

We strongly encourage all submissions to identify 1-2 themes from the above list that best describe the paper/panel topic.

The deadline for all submissions is January 10th, 2014.

For individual papers, please submit to:https://docs.google.com/forms/d/1QDnUr_NghgWxR9cYjGDg1T9njEUQa_UHCZR85Nn_OPA/viewform

For panel proposals, please submit to:https://docs.google.com/forms/d/1A4xJHI1PMmgVzXzgP0P2nkr8joDrVbKIO-DOAzEM2Z8/viewform

Please be advised that we cannot accommodate requests to present on a specific date or time slot and expect participants to be available for the full three days of the conference. The organizing committee also reserves the right to re-arrange panel proposals, if necessary. For more information please contact historicalmaterialismtoronto@gmail.com.